@GoshisDead,
You talking about your banana hammer as equal to something that measures something.
[/quote]
I certainly was not doing that. I drawing the analogy between using a hammer to bang in nails, and using a banana to bang in nails, and I was pointing out that there is no sane person who would think that a banana was as useful as a hammer for banging in nails. And I concluded that it was an objective fact that a hammer is more useful for banging in nails than a (ripe ) banana. Don't you believe that? So you have the analogy I was making all cockeyed.
Next: I don't know whether a judgment about utility (that means usefulness) is a value judgment (you seem to know about such things, but I don't claim to know whether it is a value judgment or not). But I will present this argument.
Since, as I have shown with my analogy between a hammer and a banana (
not between a hammer and a measuring instrument) (and also my analogy between a watch that keeps good time, and a watch that does not keep good time) judgments about utility can be objective judgments.
It then follows (are you keeping up?) that some value judgments are objective judgments.
More formally:
1. All judgments about utility are value judgments (that's what you maintain)
2. But some judgments about utility are objective judgments. (My examples of the hammer vs the banana, and the two watches)
Therefore, 3. Some value judgments are objective judgments. QED.
If you disagree with the conclusion of the above argument, then you must either think that the argument is invalid, or that one (or more) of the premises is false.
The argument is obviously valid.
Therefore, if you reject the conclusion, you must reject either 1. or 2. above. But 1. is what you maintain is true, and 2. has been shown true by my two examples of judgments of utility that are objective judgments. So, on what grounds do you reject the conclusion?