rufio wrote:The definition of good can only be an opinion, since it isn't universal.
If it's a definition, it must be universal. If it's not universal, it isn't a definition.
rufio wrote:Here, this may help you understand it a little better. Lets make some new adjectives. We have, for instance, the adjective good-rufio, the adjective good-joefromchicago, the adjective good-twyvel. Each of these adjectives refer to the definitions of "good" of the various people mentioned.
OK, so far.
rufio wrote:They're each universal.
Ooooh, you were so close -- and then you blew it. A subjective "definition" of good
can't be universal, at least not in any meaningful sense of the word.
rufio wrote:Assuming that we knew each other's morality, good-rufio, good-joe, and good-twyvel would universally mean the same thing, no matter what the context is.
Are you suggesting that, though everyone's morality is subjective (i.e. unique to each individual), that everyone's morality is identical? You'll have to explain that one a little better. As it stands, it's preposterous.
rufio wrote:However, they are also separate adjectives with separate meanings. So one action may be good-joe, but not good-twyvel. The model basically uses the general opening "good-____" where the blank can be filled by a name. Do you see?
Yes. "Good" is a meaningless prefix. The real definition is located in the modified subject. So "good" is identical for everyone, because it is equally meaningless for everyone.
Of course, this only pushes the definitional problem from "good" to the individual subjects. Which means that you
still haven't defined "good" (in the sense of something which is the opposite of "evil" and which you have posited
exists in some non-trivial fashion -- as opposed to "good" which is a meaningless prefix and which is, in your system, indefinable).
rufio wrote:If you think I said that we all had different definitions of "wood" you must have been mistaken, because I never meant to say anything of the sort. That did not even enter the discussion, so I don't know where you got it from. If you think the objectivity of wood is going to have any usefulness in this discussion, kindly explain why you think that is.
I didn't introduce the wood example into this discussion,
rufio, you did. If anyone should explain its significance, it should be you.
rufio wrote:You are talking about two different things - subjective perceptions of objective things, and perceptions of things that are themselves subjective. I am not talking about perceptions at all. I am talking about the things themselves.
What "things" are you talking about? Morality? Good? Evil? How are these objective "things"?
rufio wrote:Like what? There's nothing extraneous here. If you tell me what's confusing you, perhaps I can explain it.
The notion of a "placeholder" is extraneous because it's both meaningless and significant: meaningless because it represents nothing, and significant because you
want it to represent something. You started by dividing the world (or at least all actions in the world) into "good" and "evil." Now you say that "good" is a placeholder term. Are you then concluding that all actions are divided into "a meaningless placeholder" and "another meaningless placeholder"? If so, then why expend any energy on this project at all? Your argument is simply meaninglessness piled on top of meaninglessness -- it's the philosophical equivalent of multiplying everything you say by zero.
rufio wrote:I am not defining "good" by classifying actions as "good".
Funny, I thought that was
exactly what you were doing. As you mentioned earlier: "Good ...
only refers to an action that is not [
sic] the correct one to take to acheive a certain goal." All along, you've been defining "good" (to the extent that you've been defining anything in your argument) by classifying actions as either "good" or "evil."
rufio wrote:I am taking something, that, by the definition of good, is good, and calling it good. If you have a definition of "red" and find something, that's according to your definition of red, is red, than you would call it red.
You want to have "good" without actually defining "good." If you take something "that, by the definition of good, is good," then you
must have a definition of "good." And if the definition of "good" is subjective, then anything that is described as "good" is equally subjective. As such, you cannot say that an action X is "good," you can only say that "a certain person Y holds that an action X is good."
rufio wrote:Would you like to explain that, since you seem to think you know my position better than I do?
Sure. In response to my comment that people lie about their objectives, you said: "True, but those false objectives can still be judged. But this is beside the point." Yet if, as you previously stated, "the objective is not right or wrong -
the objective merely determines whether the actions were right or not," then the objective is
never beside the point. Indeed, the reality or falsity of the objective is the
central question in determining if something is good or not.
rufio wrote:Why would anyone else need to? This is about you, not them. Of course, someone else could always judge your decisions based on their moral code, as well. It's rather pointless to explain this back and forth. We could on forever, and the answer would still be the same.
If "good" is purely subjective, then there is no point in describing
any action or objective as either good or evil, since there is no standard by which an observer could judge the action or objective. In other words, if person A says "I wish to kill that stranger, and the most effective means of doing so would be to shoot the stranger with this rifle," there is no way that observer B could deem either the objective (killing the stranger) or the action (shooting the stranger) as "good," except in the trivial sense of displaying B's approval or disapproval of A's objective and action according to B's own moral code. In that case, "good" for B really means "I approve of that" rather than any kind of objective judgment.
Which brings me back to the question I asked earlier and that you refused to answer,
rufio. For your convenience, I'll repeat it:
Person A says that his action is "good." Person B says that A's action is "not-good." How are we to determine who is correct?
rufio wrote:And on the universal nature of individual morality.
How can individual morality be universal?
rufio wrote:What issue am I avoiding? If you'd mention it, I'd be happy to address it.
See above.
rufio wrote:So how would you derive it?
This isn't about me,
rufio. It's your system, you defend it.
rufio wrote:That's only true if ~(P -> Q). And that's what I'm proving is not the case in this instance. You can't assume ~(P -> Q) until you've shown it, just like you can't assume P -> Q until you've shown it.
But you still haven't put
any of your arguments in this syllogistic form. So you can't "prove" anything by what you've just said, unless you're attempting to prove Q, which, at this point, is merely the letter that comes after P.
rufio wrote:P is not exactly a premise, it's an antecedant. The Socrates argument goes (in simplified form) P = Q. Q = R. .: P = R.
Nope. In the classic syllogism "
all men are mortal: Socrates is a man: therefore Socrates is mortal" there is no middle term. Rather, it is "if P then Q; Socrates is P; therefore Socrates is Q" (in your version, "Socrates" is the first term, which is a distortion of the syllogism I put forward).
rufio wrote:My argument goes (in simplified form) .: P -> Q. There are no premises.
Your argument has no premises and
starts with a "therefore"? That's not logic, that's question-begging.
rufio wrote:P and Q are much more complicated than simple sentences, but one you express them correctly, the truth of the statment is self-evident no matter what premises you start with.
Nonsense.
rufio wrote:My antecedant is that goodness is a moral code held by a person.
You want to have a "moral code" that exists independently of the notion of "good." Yet a moral code is
nothing if it doesn't already contain within it a notion of "good." But perhaps you could explain how a moral code can dispense with the notion of "good" and still be a moral code.