Inasmuch as there never was a "factual impossibility defense" to attempt, there should be no worry on your part that something that never existed will be "revived."
Debra_Law wrote:Inasmuch as there never was a "factual impossibility defense" to attempt, there should be no worry on your part that something that never existed will be "revived."
It would be under your theory.
Defendants have been trying to argue factual impossibility since the law first criminalized attempts. And for just as long, courts have said that factual impossibility is not a defense. "Where intent and conduct evidence an attempt, one should not escape responsibility merely because he could not effectuate the intended result, due to some fortuitous circumstance not apparent to him when he acted." See People v. Moran, 25 N.E. 412, 412-13 (N.Y. 1890).
The crime of which the defendant was convicted necessarily consists of three elements: First, the act; second, the intent; and, third, the knowledge of an existing condition. There was proof tending to establish two of these elements, the first and second, but none to establish the existence of the third. This was knowledge of the stolen character of the property sought to be acquired. There could be no such knowledge. The defendant could not know that the property possessed the character of stolen property when it had not in fact been acquired by theft. The language used by Ruger, Ch. J., in People v. Moran, [p. 502] 123 N. Y. 254, 25 N. E. 412, 10 L. R. A. 109, 20 Am. St. Rep. 732, quoted with approval by Earl, J., in People v. Gardner, 144 N. Y. 119, 38 N. E. 1003, 28 L. R. A. 699, 43 Am. St. Rep. 741, to the effect that 'the question whether an attempt to commit a crime has been made is determinable solely by the condition of the actor's mind and his conduct in the attempted consummation of his design,' although accurate in those cases, has no application to a case like this, where, if the accused had completed the act which he at tempted to do, he would not be guilty of a criminal offense. A particular belief cannot make that a crime which is not so in the absence of such belief.
Factual impossibility, then, has never been a defense to an attempt crime, and that was so even under the common law definition of attempts prior to the advent of the MPC. Now, however, you want to revive factual impossibility as a defense under some mistaken notion that, under the pre-MPC common law, a defendant could successfully argue that he was unable to complete the crime because of some "fortuitous circumstance" that prevented him. Thus in Helder you admit that you would actually buy the defendant's argument that he could never have completed the crime simply because the person he thought was a minor was, in fact, an undercover police officer. But no judge, either before or after the introduction of the MPC, would have accepted Helder's argument as a defense to a charge of criminal attempt. Why you would remains a mystery.
Under a pick-pocket statute, if an actor, with intent to pick your pocket, reaches his hand into your pocket, he has committed an attempt. He had the specific intent to commit the crime plus he engaged in an overt act that came dangerously close to the commission of the actual crime.
But, the fact remains, our federal courts must apply the common law unless expressly directed otherwise by Congress. U.S. v. Morrissette. Inasmuch as our federal courts have legislated from the bench and adopted the MPC formulation (in part) to define the crime of attempt, our courts have violated the separation of powers doctrine.
The first actor, with felonious intent to kill, aims a gun at the heart of the victim and shoots. The bullet penetrates the victim's chest and the victim dies. The first actor is guilty of homicide.
The second actor, with felonious intent to kill, also aims a gun at the heart of the victim and shoots. However, the bullet hits a metal medallion and fails to penetrate the victim's chest. The victim lives. But for the "fortuitous circumstance" that the victim was wearing a metal medallion, the victim would have been killed. However, the actor's conduct came dangerously close to accomplishing the crime and he should be held criminally liable for attempt.
Under a pick-pocket statute, if an actor, with intent to pick your pocket, reaches his hand into your pocket, he has committed an attempt. He had the specific intent to commit the crime plus he engaged in an overt act that came dangerously close to the commission of the actual crime. The fact that it was impossible for the actor to commit the "last act" necessary to complete the crime (pull out your valuables because your valuables weren't in that pocket) does not negate the critical fact that the actor's conduct came dangerously close to the actual commission of the crime. Once that actor placed his hand in your pocket, that was it. If he had pulled out your valuables, the crime would be complete. Because he didn't pull out your valuables, it was an attempt. Criminal liability did not hinge on what the actor may have subjectively believed.
On the other hand, you cannot attempt to buy stolen propety unless the property is in fact stolen. If all you have done is buy property that was not stolen, an actor's subjective belief that the property was stolen does not make an act that is otherwise innocent under the law a crime. "A particular belief cannot make that a crime which is not so in the absence of such belief." The same holds true for the Helder case. It is not a crime to entice an adult.
Under the objective common law formulation, Helder's conduct does not constitute a crime. The only thing that makes Helder's conduct a crime under the MPC formulation is his erroneous belief that he was enticing a minor.
Debra_Law wrote:Under a pick-pocket statute, if an actor, with intent to pick your pocket, reaches his hand into your pocket, he has committed an attempt. He had the specific intent to commit the crime plus he engaged in an overt act that came dangerously close to the commission of the actual crime.
Not that I know anything about the matter, but this seems like a very counter-intuitive usage of the words "dangerously close" to me. It would imply that if I, a believer in voodoo, stick a needle into my doll in order to kill you, the prosecution would sue me for murder. I came "dangerously close"; the only thing standing between me and your death is that voodoo couldn't possibly kill you -- and that, according to you irrelevant....
Debra_Law wrote:The first actor, with felonious intent to kill, aims a gun at the heart of the victim and shoots. The bullet penetrates the victim's chest and the victim dies. The first actor is guilty of homicide.
The second actor, with felonious intent to kill, also aims a gun at the heart of the victim and shoots. However, the bullet hits a metal medallion and fails to penetrate the victim's chest. The victim lives. But for the "fortuitous circumstance" that the victim was wearing a metal medallion, the victim would have been killed. However, the actor's conduct came dangerously close to accomplishing the crime and he should be held criminally liable for attempt.
What of the third actor, who, with felonious intent to kill, also aims a gun at the heart of the victim and pulls the trigger, only to discover that the gun isn't loaded?
Under a pick-pocket statute, if an actor, with intent to pick your pocket, reaches his hand into your pocket, he has committed an attempt. He had the specific intent to commit the crime plus he engaged in an overt act that came dangerously close to the commission of the actual crime. The fact that it was impossible for the actor to commit the "last act" necessary to complete the crime (pull out your valuables because your valuables weren't in that pocket) does not negate the critical fact that the actor's conduct came dangerously close to the actual commission of the crime. Once that actor placed his hand in your pocket, that was it. If he had pulled out your valuables, the crime would be complete. Because he didn't pull out your valuables, it was an attempt. Criminal liability did not hinge on what the actor may have subjectively believed.
How is the empty pocket in your hypothetical any different from the undercover police officer in Helder? In the former, the pickpocket could never have committed the crime that he intended to commit, because the money that he thought was in the pocket was actually not there. In the latter, Helder could never have committed the crime that he intended to commit, because the "minor" that he thought he was enticing was actually an adult. It defies common sense to argue that the pickpocket cannot plead factual impossibility as a defense but that Helder can.
On the other hand, you cannot attempt to buy stolen propety unless the property is in fact stolen. If all you have done is buy property that was not stolen, an actor's subjective belief that the property was stolen does not make an act that is otherwise innocent under the law a crime. "A particular belief cannot make that a crime which is not so in the absence of such belief." The same holds true for the Helder case. It is not a crime to entice an adult.
And it's not a crime to put your hand in someone's empty pocket (or, if it is, it's a simple battery, not attempted theft). The only thing that distinguishes the person who puts his hand in someone else's pocket out of asbentmindedness or clumsiness and the thief who puts his hand in someone else's pocket in the expectation that there is money there is a "particular belief." Yet the former is not a crime while the latter is. In the same sense, if I shoot at a person thinking it is a mannequin, it is a far different act from that of the person who shoots a mannequin thinking it is a person. Thus, it is simply wrong to say that "a particular belief cannot make that a crime which is not so in the absence of such belief." Jaffe is wrong (in more ways than one): judges in this country issue rulings that belie that notion every day.*
Under the objective common law formulation, Helder's conduct does not constitute a crime. The only thing that makes Helder's conduct a crime under the MPC formulation is his erroneous belief that he was enticing a minor.
Which is no different from the pickpocket's erroneous belief that there was money in the pocket that he attempted to pick.
*"The reasoning in the Jaffe line of cases has come under considerable criticism in the last twenty-five years, and in response to the criticism the defense has been uniformly rejected by the highest courts of most states where the issue has been raised." Commonwealth v. Henley, 504 Pa. 408, 474 A.2d 1115 (1984)
The prosecution could make the argument, under the common law formulation, that the actor's conduct came dangerously close to the accomplishment of the actual crime. The actor's conduct of aiming the gun and pulling the trigger was likely to cause the death of another unless foiled in some way. The judge would submit the case to the jury for a determination whether the prosecution has proved each and every element of the crime of attempted murder beyond a reasonable doubt.
The difference, as stated, is that criminal liability for larceny does not hinge on what the actor may have subjectively believed.
Larceny is defined as the taking of property without the owner's consent and with the intention to permanently deprive the owner of possession of the property. When the pick pocket actor surreptitiously slips his hand into your pocket to steal the contents, he's not seeking your consent. If the actor had pulled your valuables out of your pocket, the crime would be COMPLETE. Accordingly, the act of placing a hand in your pocket comes dangerously close to accomplishing the actual crime of larceny.
Enticement is defined as knowingly attempting to entice a minor with the intention of engaging in sexual activity that would constitute a criminal offense. When Helder attempted to contact a minor, he did so with the intent to entice. If Helder had enticed a minor, the crime would be COMPLETE. Accordingly, the act of contacting someone for the purposes of enticement comes dangerously close to accomplishing the actual crime of enticement.
On the other hand, criminal liability in the Helder case hinged entirely on what Helder subjectively believed. Helder did not entice a minor. His conduct did not come dangerously close to accomplishing the actual crime of enticing a minor.
You are basing your argument on a false analogy.
"Criminal penalties may be inflicted only if the accused has commited some act, has engaged in some behavior, which society has an interest in preventing." Powell v. Texas, 392, U.S. 514, 533 (1968) (discussing Robinson v. California, 370 U.S. 660 (1962)).
In the example given immediately preceding your response, the conduct that society seeks to prevent is receiving STOLEN property. It is not a crime to receive property if the property isn't stolen. Under the common law, an erroneous belief that the property is stolen cannot make that a crime which is not so in the absence of such belief.
In Helder's case, the conduct that society seeks to prevent is enticing a minor. It is not a crime to entice an adult. Under the common law, an erroneous belief that the person is a minor cannot make that a crime which is not so in the absence of such belief.
With respect to the pick pocket (larceny) example, you have to ask the question: What is the conduct that society seeks to prevent? Answer:
The conduct that society seeks to prevent is the wrongful taking of the property of another without the owner's consent. Here's the true and relevant analogy: It is not a crime to take the property of another if the owner consents. An erroneous belief that owner did not consent to the taking, when in fact the owner did consent, cannot make that a crime which is not so in the absence of such belief.
You based your argument on a the FALSE ANALOGY. If you use a true and relevant analogy as set forth above, your argument falls apart.
As set forth above, you used a false analogy. The pickpocket's criminal liability does NOT hinge upon his erroneous belief that there is something valuable in your pocket. The pickpocket is criminally liable because his conduct came dangerously close to the actual commission of the crime of larceny wherein society seeks to prevent the wrongful taking of property without the consent of the owner.
If, however, the pickpocket was acting under the erroneous belief that he didn't have the owner's consent, when in fact he did have the owner's consent, then--under the common law--his conduct did not come dangerously close to committing the crime of taking property without the owner's consent. Then--and ONLY then when we use the true analogy--the pickpocket's erroneous belief is no different than Helder's erroneous belief, and neither one would be held criminally liable for attempt under the COMMON LAW.
However, BOTH would be held liable for attempt under the MPC formulation due to their erroneous beliefs. The pickpocket would be criminally liable because he believed he did not have the owner's consent to take the property when in fact he did have the owner's consent; and Helder would be criminally liable because he believed he was enticing a minor when in fact he was not enticing a minor. The substantive effect of the MPC with respect to cases involving legal impossibilities is to punish the actor's guilty mind regardless of the fact that the actor's conduct is not criminal and, therefore, could not possibly come dangerously close to the actual commission of the crime.
The criticism is that Jaffe's conduct, although not criminal as an attempt at common law, was morally reprehensible.
Not that I know anything about the matter, but this seems like a very counter-intuitive usage of the words "dangerously close" to me. It would imply that if I, a believer in voodoo, stick a needle into my doll in order to kill you, the prosecution would sue me for murder. I came "dangerously close"; the only thing standing between me and your death is that voodoo couldn't possibly kill you -- and that, according to you irrelevant.
And somehow, while the prosecution could make that argument, my defense could not reply that you can't really kill with voodoo, so I am not actually guilty for attempted murder? Not saying you're wrong, but it does sound strange. Interesting, but strange.
Thomas wrote:Not that I know anything about the matter, but this seems like a very counter-intuitive usage of the words "dangerously close" to me. It would imply that if I, a believer in voodoo, stick a needle into my doll in order to kill you, the prosecution would sue me for murder. I came "dangerously close"; the only thing standing between me and your death is that voodoo couldn't possibly kill you -- and that, according to you irrelevant.
And somehow, while the prosecution could make that argument, my defense could not reply that you can't really kill with voodoo, so I am not actually guilty for attempted murder? Not saying you're wrong, but it does sound strange. Interesting, but strange.
Not surprisingly, I think Debra_Law's response to your post was incorrect.
Under the MPC standard, I don't think there could be a successful prosecution here -- not because the crime is impossible, but because the defendant did not take any act that was a substantial step toward completing the crime of murder.* Someone who intends to kill and sticks pins in a doll is no different from someone who intends to kill and does nothing else. The law does not punish bad thoughts, nor does it punish bad thoughts accompanied by innocuous deeds. Sticking pins in a doll is not analogous to a pickpocket's fruitless attempt to steal from an empty pocket, since in the latter case putting a hand into a pocket is an act that is in furtherance of a crime (albeit in this instance an unsuccessful one), whereas in the former case sticking pins in a doll is an act that does not further any crime. In the pickpocket's case, he is thwarted because of particular circumstances of which he was unaware. In the voodoo practitioner's case, he is thwarted because of the way the world works.
*Upon reflection, I now disagree with what I wrote to you in this post regarding the legal culpability of the voodoo murderer.
Under the MPC, any act at all can serve as the actus reus of an attempt as long as the actor believes it will further his or her intended criminal purpose. If an actor believes that sticking a pin into a doll will cause the death of the intended victim, then the act of sticking a pin into a doll is sufficient to constitute a substantial step.
Throughout this thread, Joe has consistently rejected the common law application of an objective approach to the law of attempt with respect to the essential actus reus element. Now, however, in his unsurprising desire to once again claim that Debra Law is wrong, he now embraces the very thing he has been arguing against. He now claims that sticking a pin in a doll, from an objective standpoint, is the same as doing nothing at all. In making his current claim, he is using the very same argument that the common law approach embraced: "The law does not punish bad thoughts."
How many times have I said that that exact same thing only to have Joe jump in and declare that I am wrong.
Regardless of Joe's desire to contradict everything I say, what I wrote about the difference between the common law formulation and the MPC formulation is correct. The common law, when analyzing the actus reus, takes an objective approach and focuses on the dangerousness of the actor's conduct. When the conduct comes dangerously close to accomplishing the actual crime, then the actor is criminally liable for attempt.
The MPC, when analyzing the actus reus, takes a subjective approach and focuses on the dangerousness of the actor's mind. Any act that corroborates the actor's criminal purpose or intent is sufficient to constitute a substantial step.
Debra_Law wrote:The prosecution could make the argument, under the common law formulation, that the actor's conduct came dangerously close to the accomplishment of the actual crime. The actor's conduct of aiming the gun and pulling the trigger was likely to cause the death of another unless foiled in some way. The judge would submit the case to the jury for a determination whether the prosecution has proved each and every element of the crime of attempted murder beyond a reasonable doubt.
Wow.
It took you almost two days to come up with a response to my post and that is the best you can do? Really, Debra, it is to laugh.
Inasmuch as my time is also valuable, I am not inclined to go through the remainder of your post and again point out your use of ad hominem attacks, strawmen arguments, and false analogies. You have clearly demonstrated that you can't identify the essential elements of substantive crimes and attempted crimes, and you can't distinguish between the mens rea element of a crime and the actus reus element of a crime, so it remains a waste of time to continue to explain the difference between the common law and the MPC with respect to the actus reus element of the crime of criminal attempt.