Scrat wrote:Believing someone should forfeit his or her life for extreme criminal acts does not mean you wish that person to suffer. I'm puzzled as to why you think the two go hand in hand.
Puzzled? Re-read my post. I gave my explanation there.
At the point where the state decides to execute someone, the manner of the condemned's death is no longer a concern solely (or even primarily) of the condemned. Since the state has decided to kill for reasons of policy, the manner of death should
serve that policy. Otherwise (as I mentioned before), it is simply murder.
What, then, is that policy? Proponents of the death penalty typically cite two rationales: (1) deterrence; and (2) retribution. In both cases, it would seem that the most
cruel form of execution should be employed: (1) because it would have more deterrent value (a horrible, painful death would, presumably, deter more criminals); and (2) a cruel death is arguably more "retributive" than an "easy" one. Making the execution
less cruel, in contrast, runs counter to the policy reasons for having executions in the first place. Not only is it hypocritical to advocate both the death penalty and the "least cruel methods" of execution, but it is
bad policy to do so.
patiodog wrote:And there's that little caveat in the constitution about cruel and unusual punishment. Now, just about everybody is a little selective in when they actually care about constitutionality, but I imagine it's pretty important to death penalty advocates that they don't offer up easy grounds on which their preferred mode of punishment can be declared unconstitutional.
Certainly, from a practical political perspective, the Eighth Amendment's strictures against "cruel and unusual punishment" effectively outlaw the kinds of executions that death penalty proponents
should be supporting. But then their proper response should be to advocate the repeal of the Eighth Amendment rather than emasculate the institution of capital punishment.