@Aedes,
Quote:And I think it's fairly obvious that he's NOT making a formal scientific assertion about the brain, but rather simplifying a complex topic by anthropomorphizing it.
I'll readily admit, and I think I have done this, that he is not making a claim, or body of claims, that should be strictly taken in, say, a scientific journal. However, what
is the nature of this claim? What
is he doing exactly? He might not be an eliminative materialist, but this is exactly my point. I do not at allow wish to argue with you over what the conditions are for some claim or some text to be considered "scientific." I could ask you "just what does 'formal' mean?" But I will not. This is a philosophy forum, and this my opponent is a philosophical school/thesis: eliminative materialism. Their claim is explicit that our "folk psychological predicates" do not exist. Their justification is scientific, in that they claim "beliefs" will be eliminated like how witches and phlogiston were shown not to exist.
Whether or not they take themselves to be scientists or whether or not scientists do X, Y or Z is not my concern. (A concern we have been preoccupied with.) I'll readily admit that scientist must write "pop" when they need to pay the bills or to cater to the baseline intellect of their audience. In a sense, every author must write to his or her intended audience. This much is, and has been clear to me. Thus, I do not need it explained to me, as if it were to explain away what my claim is. My claim is that Crick is advancing a claim to
push the boundaries of what counts as scientific. I explicitly and absolutely deny that he is simply writing shorthand or writing for a
particular audience. He is making a claim that is to pass off as valid science, just as the eliminative materialists do.
Quote:I think you are most certainly missing the context. This is a simplification of what probably amounts to a whole body of research. Anthropomorphizing or personalizing the brain may be a lot more digestible to this chosen audience than presenting the entirety demonstrable science behind his subject. Furthermore, what if in the following pages or chapters he overtly clarifies what it means when he says "the brain believes"?
Now, perhaps, we have a fundamental disagreement about explanation. "To simplify," under my understanding, means to "explain in a simpler way."
First, he's not using believes*, as opposed to believes.
Second, "anthropomorphization" is not to explain anything, but only to mislead. To anthropomorphize is not to
explain. Now the question is: Is he attempting to explain or merely describe? Description in anthropomorphic terms turns into nothing but fanciful metaphor. Explanation in anthropomorphic terms explains nothing at all.
Quote:Try and teach Wittgenstein to a group of 7th graders. It's neither condescension nor pretense to rephrase something for a lay audience. I tend to use analogies as my tact when I present complex medical issues to patients -- I explain homeostasis mechanisms in terms of a bathtub, for instance (balancing the amount coming through the faucet with the amount leaving in the drain). Is that dumbing it down, when I should really be explaining it in terms of hematopoiesis or natriuresis or whatever? Maybe, but I'm not going to get anywhere with jargon.
I don't really understand the analogy. As what we are dealing with here is a particular claim about the nature of the brain and its capacities. "teach Wittgenstein" is so over-general that it would be misleading to compare teaching an entire philosopher's System (or "therapeutic system," in Wittgenstein's case) to the nature of the brain. Whether or not one can, I highly doubt, really gets us any closer to the heart of our contention.
I really would like to attack this notion of mere "analogy." "Anthropomorphization" is a particular kind of analogy. So I should not be taken, by my attack on anthropomorphization, to be arguing that analogy is useless. Indeed, as anyone should know who has come across Wittgenstein, a majority of his better arguments were analogy. Thus, I struggle to see how, as a self-proclaimed Wittgensteinian, you might even consider that I wish to attack analogy as a viable source for explanation. I certainly hope you have not ventured to consider those thoughts.
But back to my main point. You have made the explicit move which suggests that "analogy(anthropomorphization)" and "analogy(physical process)" are equally innocuous explanatory devices. This I most certainly disagree with, if not simply to point out that
they are two different classes of analogy and we should inspect both classes as distinguished from one another. This is the reason we why we (informal) fallacies identified as "false analogy," to help us distinction the poor and irrelevant analogies from to proper, relevant and helpful ones. Saying that a brain has a believe is not just some analogical device that is
just as innocuous as saying "gravity works like this."
Quote:Feel free to look up my most recent publication (Lantos et al, Parasitology (2009), 136, 1-9), I'm the first author. How readable is this to someone who is not a biologist? I don't know how much teaching experience you have, but peer-to-peer communications are NOT going to work for a lay audience or even an audience of students. And a lot of popularizations we have (like Stephen Hawking's books, or Stephen Jay Gould's books) are specifically written (and therefore successful!) because of their accessibility. If one ever needs more detail about the science, the original references are always there.
Again, we can make a distinction. Those who are actually making claims about the brain that are not to be taken as "mere analogy" and those who are. The writers you have cited perhaps do frequently use explicit analogy and wish to be taken as doing so. For one thing, it must be noted that neuroscientific research isn't
just like theoretical physics or biology. The object of study, presumably, is belief. Exploration of the galaxy, the "beginning of time," black holes, dark energy, microorganisms, viruses, etc are not
like beliefs. So it should not be surprising, I think, that when a neuroscientist decides to treat beliefs, thoughts, and such as if they were just like any other physical phenomena, that the debate take a somewhat different turn.
Again, it is fully understood that analogy is employed, and it rightfully should be. But
this is not analogy. Further, and this is why I make such a point in the last paragraph, I think it unfair to bring in the areas of (micro)biology and (theoretical) physics when we're talking about a particular scientific discourse that is very much different from these.
Now, to explicitly address your claim to the validity of "analogy" in explanation. It should be point out that I am being charitable here, though I need not be. Again, by addressing analogical reasoning, I need not be taken to be addressing anthropomorphization (for it is a particular, and thus more specific, class of analogy). We could easily, I think, drop anthroporphization while still legitimately using analogy in explanation, given the right audience and context.
It must be admitted (as it cannot be argued otherwise) that Crick, for instance, is using the term "believe" and ascribing that predicate to the brain. This much is clear. He is using the letters "B," "E," "L," and so on. He is using this term, belief, in its traditional grammatical way (as is evidenced by the sentence). Whether or not he
means something "highly technical" or "has references which support its use" is the argument I now address. Thus, since he is using the concept of belief (as is obvious by the quote), now the question is what does he mean by it. But stronger: The question is:
What could he mean by it? I would like, as is clear by this stronger question, resolve this matter by eliminating the possible argument that we'd need to
read the whole of his text or a great majority of it, along with all its sources and references to get at what he means. By this stronger question, I wish to drive at this point: He, whether he knew it or not, mistakenly made a nonsensical claim.
So
your defense amounts to (with charitable interpretation) roughly these:
(1) He's using a technical term. (Belief is really Belief*)
(2) He's using analogy (analogical extension of the predicate "to believe").
(3) He's speaking metaphorically.
Counters:
(1) It's clear that he is not using a technical term, for he would have chosen a different term. Nothing about what is quote suggests that "believe" is being used in a "highly technical sense." "Belief," under its conventional sense presupposes interpretation, past experience and information (that which is the outcome and mediating constitutive element to the act of interpretation). Should Crick or any other author use "belief" in some technical sense (belief*), then that author would have to provide definitions of interpretation*, past experience*, information* and many other concepts which are embedded in the concept of "belief." Not only would the text be cumbersome, but it certainly would not cater to a "lay audience." For why would anyone wish to sit down to read a text which tells them that seeing* is in fact what you're really doing, while believing*, feeling*, expressing*, uttering*, etc, etc, etc are all the right concepts. Essentially, you'd be sitting down to read a radical re-write of your entire vocabulary. Even if you disagree with me, I implore you to at least stop and reflect on this argument. It is, as is obvious, the one I raised previously (about concepts being chained together or deeply interconnected).
(2) In my reading, I have not come to the conclusion that mere analogy is being used. As with the technical sense claim (1), I take these authors to be not introducing bloated terms or introducing analogy. They intend for these terms to be taken in their conventional meaning, but simply ascribed to the wrong (the brain) category or thing. For instance, a hemisphere of the brain is "a conscious system in its own right, perceiving, thinking, remembering, reasoning, willing and emoting, all at a characteristically human level" (Sperry, "Lateral specialization in the surgically separated hemispheres").
Again, I'd like point this out: Neuroscience (and thus neuroscientific literature) should not be uncritically and easily placed in the same safe zone as, say, (non-theoretical) physics, biology, chemistry, etc. If anything, neuroscientific and cognitive neuroscientific literature, I think, resembles the more "wacky" theoretical literature of physics, the highly contentious stuff (M-theory, string theory, multiverse theory, etc). If you disagree, that's fine. But at least I'd like you to try on the spectacles I'm wearing. See if you sit easy when you come across statements which claim that the acquisition of knowledge is a "primordial function of the brain" (Semir Zeki, "Abstraction and idealism").
Surely, the immediate tug is to think, "Ah, he must mean knowledge*, not knowledge like what I'm concerned with, like learning about the U.S. government's history." Does he
really mean knowledge*, and not knowledge in its conventional sense? And if he does not mean knowledge*, then why should we even care about his claims. As with any scientific jargon, if you tell me, "You don't believe* that" (which is just to say, on hypothesis that eliminative materialism is true, my brain is not believing that) then I might simply ignore you. In a less extreme example, as with any jargon, we fail to see its relevance in practical cases. I find nothing interesting to learn about Ghandi's beliefs* or his thoughts*.
Further, and to my point, if merely analogical extensions, then the boundaries (the semantic field) of the term so extended must also be justified
along with the combinatorial possibilities that term plays in various other semantic contexts.
(3) "A map is not a territory" (Korzybski). A great slogan, I think, and it is relevant to this metaphor claim. A human's believing is not some charting of neuron states. We might find correlations (as this is what maps are intended to do; they're approximations, in principle). So if we say that a brain's belief are metaphorical, then we might have to apply the same reasoning here: the brain has some level of activity going on that simply is not charted, in principle, by its beliefs. But the whole premise of the neuroscientific endeavor is to chart the activity of the brain and make inductive generalizations. So on its face it is senseless and circular to talk about the brain's beliefs. And if he means beliefs*, then even worse.
Of course, this is very long, and I hope you do not think I simply went off on a tangent. His statement, and many other statements based upon (in philosophical) and found in neuroscientific literature, have this quality of ascribing predicates to the brain. But more to your point: What if he defined his terms in a particular way? Well, I should hope (1)-(3) respond to that. Why should we care about jargon? How can he account for the interconnectedness of concepts like belief? Calling it metaphor simply admits the error and explains nothing.