Thomas wrote:Debra_Law wrote:1. The enumeration of some individual rights in the constitution that are secured against goverment oppression shall not be construed to deny or disparage all other unenumerated rights retained by the people.
Of course.
But the converse is not true -- not everything that the constitution left unenumerated is an unenumerated right retained by the people. As a practical matter, then, how would you find out which unenumerated interests are rights protected under the Ninth amendment, and which are not?
You're wrong, Thomas. The Ninth amendment is not a source of substantive protection of unenumerated rights; it is a rule of constitutional construction. Accordingly, when you claim that "abortion" (more specifically, a woman's liberty interest in determining for herself whether to continue or terminate a pregnancy and to control her own procreative destiny without unreasonable government interference) is
not mentioned in the Constitution and is not protected, you are engaging in the very evil act of constitutional construction that the founders sought to prevent by the Ninth Amendment.
Justice Goldberg wrote:In presenting the proposed Amendment, Madison said:
"It has been objected also against a bill of rights, that, by enumerating particular exceptions to the grant of power, it would disparage those rights which were not placed in that enumeration; and it might follow by implication, that those rights which were not singled out, were intended to be assigned into the hands of the General Government, and were consequently insecure. This is one of the most plausible arguments I have ever heard urged against the admission of a bill of rights into this system; but, I conceive, that it may be guarded against. I have attempted it, as gentlemen may see by turning to the [381 U.S. 479, 490] last clause of the fourth resolution [the Ninth Amendment]." I Annals of Congress 439 (Gales and Seaton ed. 1834)
. . . To hold that a right so basic and fundamental and so deep-rooted in our society as the right of privacy in marriage may be infringed because that right is not guaranteed in so many words by the first eight amendments to the Constitution is to ignore the Ninth Amendment and to give it no effect whatsoever. Moreover, a judicial construction that this fundamental right is not protected by the Constitution because it is not mentioned in explicit terms by one of the first eight amendments or elsewhere in the Constitution would violate the Ninth Amendment, which specifically states that "[t]he enumeration in the Constitution, of certain rights, shall not be construed to deny or disparage others retained by the people."
Source:
GRISWOLD v. CONNECTICUT, 381 U.S. 479 (1965)(Goldberg, J., concurring).
You're operating under the false premise that there are some rights or liberty interests that are not protected simply because they are not mentioned in the Constitution or do not rise to the level of a "fundamental" right. Certainly, wearing a cap backwards at a county fair is not a right mentioned in the Constitution nor has any court ruled that it is a "fundamental" right, but the Constitution nevertheless protects that liberty interest from arbitrary government infringement.
Some people fail to understand that the Constitution secures ALL liberty, great and small, against unreasonable, arbitrary, or oppressive government denials or deprivations--which is the very essense of substantive due process. Although the Court will review infringements of rights deemed to be fundamental with a higher level of scrutiny, even NON-fundamental rights are protected against arbitrary, unreasonable, or oppressive infringements. At a minimum, ALL government enactments or conduct (the means used) affecting life, liberty, or property must be rationally related (reasonable) to serve a LEGITIMATE government interest. When statutes are challenged on their face or as applied on due process grounds, the courts examine the
substance of the law to determine whether the ends are LEGITIMATE (within the power of the government) and whether the means chosen (e.g., a deprivation of liberty in whatever form it takes) are justified.
Debra_Law wrote:As a society progresses and matures, punishments that might have been acceptable and common 230 years ago (e.g., the execution of children and/or incompetents) might be construed by the people to be the product of uncivilized ignorance and become uncommon.
Thomas wrote:I know that by saying this, I am coming dangerously close to triggering Godwin's law. But I can't help being a German with a sense of history, so it never fails to amaze me how naively Americans take it for granted that their society progresses and matures. How does your principle apply when society regresses and falls apart, and a large number of people find it's okay again to execute all kinds of undesireables? If this happened in America, do you think a court would be justified in arguing that 'maturity', properly interpreted, now means the state can mass-deport dissidents to Sibiria? (Guantanamo Bay I guess.)
Here's what Scalia says about executing undesireables:
Justice Scalia wrote:I want to make clear at the outset of my remarks that what I will have to say or, for that matter, what I have heard at this very interesting conference has nothing to do with how I vote in capital cases that come before the Supreme Court. That statement would not be true if I subscribed to the conventional fallacy that the Constitution is a living document; that is, a text that means from age to age whatever the society or perhaps the Court thinks it ought to mean. In recent years, that philosophy has been particularly well enshrined in our Eighth Amendment jurisprudence; that is, our case law dealing with the prohibition dealing with cruel and unusual punishments. Several of our opinions have stated that what falls within this prohibition is not static but changes from generation to generation to comport with “the evolving standards of decency that mark the progress of a maturing society.”
. . . If I subscribe to the proposition that I am authorized – indeed, I suppose, compelled – to intuit and impose our maturing society’s evolving standards of decency, this conference would be for me a sort of continuing judicial education. As it is, however, the Constitution that I interpret and apply is not living, but dead; or as I prefer to call it, enduring. (Laughter.) It means today not what current society, much less the Court, thinks it ought to mean, but what it meant when it was adopted. For me, therefore, the constitutionality of the death penalty is not a difficult, soul-wrenching question. It was clearly permitted when the Eighth Amendment was adopted – not merely for murder, by the way, but for all felonies, including, for example, horse thieving, as anyone can verify by watching a western movie. And so it is clearly permitted today as far as the Constitution is concerned.
Source:
A Call for Reckoning: Religion & the Death Penalty.
According to Scalia, a state government may choose to define any undesireable conduct (picking pockets and stealing chickens) as a criminal felony and impose the penalty of death without violating the "original meaning" of the Eighth Amendment. Therefore, your fear that society will regress and start executing all kinds of undesireables is more likely to be realized under Scalia's interpretation of the Eighth Amendment as the floor constitutional protection against cruel and unusal punishments as opposed to justices who apply modern day standards as the floor constitutional protection against cruel and unsual punishments.
The level of punishment applied for the violation of criminal law is tied to the offender's culpability. The Court has determined that the government does NOT have a LEGITIMATE interest in treating less culpable offenders (children and incompetents) as harshly as other more culpable offenders. Once the floor constitutional protection has been established against cruel and unusual punishments, our adherence to precedent forbids the government from dropping below the floor and operating in the basement.
Debra_Law wrote:The phrase "due process of law" means the same thing today that it meant throughout time which embodies the "law of the land" as the law exists when it is applied (not how the law might have existed 230 years ago) and requires the application of LEGITIMATE laws that provide both substantive fairness and procedural fairness.
Thomas wrote:Can you show me a founding era (or earlier) example where a court struck down a law on substantive due process grounds?
In 1798, Justice Chase wrote the following:
The people of the United States erected their Constitutions, or forms of government, to establish justice, to promote the general welfare, to secure the blessings of liberty; and to protect their persons and property from violence. The purposes for which men enter into society will determine the nature and terms of the social compact; and as they are the foundation of the legislative power, they will decide what are the proper objects of it: The nature, and ends of legislative power will limit the exercise of it. . . .
There are acts which the Federal, or State, Legislature cannot do, without exceeding their authority. There are certain vital principles in our free Republican governments, which will determine and over-rule an apparent and flagrant abuse of legislative power; as to authorize manifest injustice by positive law; or to take away that security for personal liberty, or private property, for the protection whereof of the government was established. An ACT of the Legislature (for I cannot call it a law) contrary to the great first principles of the social compact, cannot be considered a rightful exercise of legislative authority. The obligation of a law in governments established on express compact, and on republican principles, must be determined by the nature of the power, on which it is founded. . . .
It is against all reason and justice, for a people to entrust a Legislature with SUCH powers; and, therefore, it cannot be presumed that they have done it. The genius, the nature, and the spirit, of our State Governments, amount to a prohibition of such acts of legislation; and the general principles of law and reason forbid them.
CALDER v. BULL, 3 U.S. 386 (1798).
http://laws.findlaw.com/us/3/386.html
The people instituted the government to secure liberty; the people never delegated power to the government to enact arbitrary or oppressive laws. Example of one of our founder's views:
"
The Legislative has no right to absolute, arbitrary power over the lives and fortunes of the people. The Legislative cannot justly assume to itself a power to rule by extempore arbitrary decrees…" Samuel Adams, The Rights of the Colonists (1772).
A substantive due process analysis reviews the SUBSTANCE of the challenged government enactment to determine whether it falls within the legitimate powers of government (within a legitimate power delegated by the people to government) and whether the means used are reasonable and just. Our founding society (the "give me liberty or give me death" generation) never tolerated the notion that the government may arbitrarily enact laws that deny or disparage their life, liberty, or property interests.
Justice Souter briefly outlined the history of "due process of law" in his concurring opinion in WASHINGTON et al. v. GLUCKSBERG et al. as follows:
Justice Souter wrote:Before the ratification of the Fourteenth Amendment, substantive constitutional review resting on a theory of unenumerated rights occurred largely in the state courts applying state constitutions that commonly contained either due process clauses like that of the Fifth Amendment (and later the Fourteenth) or the textual antecedents of such clauses, repeating Magna Carta's guarantee of "the law of the land." 5 On the basis of such clauses, or of general principles untethered to specific constitutional language, state courts evaluated the constitutionality of a wide range of statutes.
Thus, a Connecticut court approved a statute legitimating a class of previous illegitimate marriages, as falling within the terms of the "social compact," while making clear its power to review constitutionality in those terms. Goshen v. Stonington, 4 Conn. 209, 225-226 (1822). In the same period, a specialized court of equity, created under a Tennessee statute solely to hear cases brought by the state bank against its debtors, found its own authorization unconstitutional as "partial" legislation violating the state constitution's "law of the land" clause. Bank of the State v. Cooper, 2 Yerg. 599, 602-608 (Tenn. 1831) (Green, J.); id., at 613-615 (Peck, J.); id., at 618-623 (Kennedy, J.). And the middle of the 19th century brought the famous Wynehamer case, invalidating a statute purporting to render possession of liquor immediately illegal except when kept for narrow, specified purposes, the state court finding the statute inconsistent with the state's due process clause. Wynehamer v. People, 13 N. Y. 378, 486-487 (1856). The statute was deemed an excessive threat to the "fundamental rights of the citizen" to property. Id., at 398 (Comstock, J.). See generally, E. Corwin, Liberty Against Government 58-115 (1948) (discussing substantive due process in the state courts before the Civil War); T. Cooley, Constitutional Limitations *85%*129, *351%*397.
Even in this early period, however, this Court anticipated the developments that would presage both the Civil War and the ratification of the Fourteenth Amendment, by making it clear on several occasions that it too had no doubt of the judiciary's power to strike down legislation that conflicted with important but unenumerated principles of American government. In most such instances, after declaring its power to invalidate what it might find inconsistent with rights of liberty and property, the Court nevertheless went on to uphold the legislative acts under review. See, e.g., Wilkinson v. Leland, 2 Pet. 627, 656-661 (1829); Calder v. Bull, 3 Dall. 386, 386-395 (1798) (opinion of Chase, J.); see also Corfield v. Coryell, 6 F. Cas. 546, 550-552 (No. 3,230) (1823). But in Fletcher v. Peck, 6 Cranch 87 (1810), the Court went further. It struck down an act of the Georgia legislature that purported to rescind a sale of public land ab initio and reclaim title for the State, and so deprive subsequent, good faith purchasers of property conveyed by the original grantees. The Court rested the invalidation on alternative sources of authority: the specific prohibitions against bills of attainder, ex post-facto laws, laws impairing contracts in Article I, § 10 of the Constitution; and "general principles which are common to our free institutions," by which Chief Justice Marshall meant that a simple deprivation of property by the State could not be an authentically "legislative" act. Fletcher, 6 Cranch, at 135-139.
Fletcher was not, though, the most telling early example of such review. For its most salient instance in this Court before the adoption of the Fourteenth Amendment was, of course, the case that the Amendment would in due course overturn, Dred Scott v. Sandford, 19 How. 393 (1857). Unlike Fletcher, Dred Scott was textually based on a due process clause (in the Fifth Amendment, applicable to the national government), and it was in reliance on that clause's protection of property that the Court invalidated the Missouri Compromise. 19 How., at 449-452. This substantive protection of an owner's property in a slave taken to the territories was traced to the absence of any enumerated power to affect that property granted to the Congress by Article I of the Constitution, id., at 451-452, the implication being that the government had no legitimate interest that could support the earlier congressional compromise. The ensuing judgment of history needs no recounting here.
After the ratification of the Fourteenth Amendment, with its guarantee of due process protection against the States, interpretation of the words "liberty" and "property" as used in due process clauses became a sustained enterprise, with the Court generally describing the due process criterion in converse terms of reasonableness or arbitrariness. That standard is fairly traceable to Justice Bradley's dissent in the Slaughter House Cases, 16 Wall. 36 (1873), in which he said that a person's right to choose a calling was an element of liberty (as the calling, once chosen, was an aspect of property) and declared that the liberty and property protected by due process are not truly recognized if such rights may be "arbitrarily assailed," id., at 116. 6 After that, opinions comparable to those that preceded Dred Scott expressed willingness to review legislative action for consistency with the Due Process Clause even as they upheld the laws in question. See, e.g., Bartemeyer v. Iowa, 18 Wall. 129, 133-135 (1874); Munn v. Illinois, 94 U.S. 113, 123 -135 (1877); Railroad Comm'n Cases, 116 U.S. 307, 331 (1886); Mugler v. Kansas, 123 U.S. 623, 659 -670 (1887). See generally Corwin, Liberty Against Government, at 121-136 (surveying the Court's early Fourteenth Amendment cases and finding little dissent from the general principle that the Due Process Clause authorized judicial review of substantive statutes). . . .
See also Justice Marshall's opinion in McCulloch v. Maryland, 17 U.S. 316 (1819) wherein Justice Marshall discussed that the MEANS chosen by government to accomplish some END must be appropriate and serve a LEGITIMATE government interest:
Justice Marshall wrote:We admit, as all must admit, that the powers of the government are limited, and that its limits are not to be transcended. But we think the sound construction of the constitution must allow to the national legislature that discretion, with respect to the means by which the powers it confers are to be carried into execution, which will enable that body to perform the high duties assigned to it, in the manner most beneficial to the people. Let the end be legitimate, let it be within the scope of the constitution, and all means which are appropriate, which are plainly adapted to that end, which are not prohibited, but consist with the letter and spirit of the constitution, are constitutional.
http://laws.findlaw.com/us/17/316.html
From the very beginning, our founders recognized that it was not appropriate for the government to enact statutes that deny or disparage individual life, liberty, or property interests unless the statute served a LEGITIMATE government interest and the means used were plainly adapted (appropriate, reasonable, and just; not arbitrary, unreasonable, or oppressive) to that LEGITIMATE end. That is the very essence of substantive due process.
Another case,
HURTADO v. PEOPLE OF STATE OF CALIFORNIA, 110 U.S. 516 (1884), reviews the history of due process of law and also notes that the SUBSTANCE of the law, not just the procedures employed, must be reasonable and just and serve a legitimate government interest:
Quote:The supreme court of California, in the judgment now under review, followed its own previous decision in Kalloch v. Super. Ct. 56 Cal. 229, in which the question was deliberately adjudged. Its conclusion was there stated as follows: 'This proceeding, as [it] is regulated by the constitution and laws of this state, is not opposed to any of the definitions given of the phrases 'due process of law' and 'the law of the land;' but, on the contrary, it is a proceeding strictly within such definitions, as much so in every respect as is a proceeding by indictment. It may be questioned whether the proceeding by indictment secures to the accused any superior rights and privileges; but certainly a prosecution by information takes from him no immunity or protection to which he is entitled under the law.' And the opinion cites and relies upon a decision of the supreme court of Wisconsin in the case of Rowan v. State, 30 Wis. 129. In that case the court, speaking of the fourteenth amendment, says: 'But its design was not to confine the states to a particular mode of procedure in judicial proceedings, and prohibit them from [110 U.S. 516, 521] prosecuting for felonies by information instead of by indictment, if they chose to abolish the grand jury system. And the words 'due process of law' in the amendment do not mean and have not the effect to limit the powers of state governments to prosecutions for crime by indictment; but these words do mean law in its regular course of administration, according to prescribed forms, and in accordance with the general rules for the protection of individual rights. Administration and remedial proceedings must change, from time to time, with the advancement of legal science and the progress of society; and, if the people of the state find it wise and expedient to abolish the grand jury and prosecute all crimes by information, there is nothing in our state constitution and nothing in the fourteenth amendment to the constitution of the United States which prevents them from doing so.'
On the other hand, it is maintained on behalf of the plaintiff in error that the phrase 'due process of law' is equivalent to 'law of the land,' as found in the twenty-ninth chapter of Magna Charta; that by immemorial usage it has acquired a fixed, definite, and technical meaning; that it refers to and includes, not only the general principles of public liberty and private right, which lie at the foundation of all free government, but the very institutions which, venerable by time and custom, have been tried by experience and found fit and necessary for the preservation of those principles. . . .
. . . The principle and true meaning of the phrase have never been more tersely or accurately stated than by Mr. Justice JOHNSON in Bank of Columbia v. Okely, 4 Wheat. 235-244: 'As to the words from Magna Charta, incorporated into the constitution of Maryland, after volumes spoken and written with a view to their exposition, the good sense of mankind has at last settled down to this: that they were intended to secure the individual from the arbitrary exercise of the powers of government, unrestrained by the established principles of private right and distributive justice.' And the conclusion rightly deduced is as stated by Mr. Cooley, (Const. Lim. 356:) 'The principles, then, upon which the process is based, are to determine whether it is 'due process' or not, and not any considerations of mere form. Administrative and remedial process may [110 U.S. 516, 528] be changed from time to time, but only with due regard to the landmarks established for the protection of the citizen.'
. . . But to hold that such a characteristic is essential to due process of law, would be to deny every quality of the law but its age, and to render it incapable of progress or improvement. It would be to stamp upon our jurisprudence the unchangeableness attributed to the laws of the Medes and Persians. . . .
. . . This flexibility and capacity for growth and adaptation is the peculiar boast and excellence of the common law. Sir JAMES MACKINTOSH ascribes this principle of development to Magna Charta itself. To use his own language: 'It was a peculiar advantage that the consequences of its principles were, if we may so speak, only discovered slowly and gradually. It gave out on each occasion only so much of the spirit of liberty and reformation as the circumstances of succeeding generations required, and as their character would safely bear; for almost five centuries it was appealed to as the decisive authority on behalf of the people, though commonly so far only as the necessities of each case demanded.' 1 Hist. Eng. 221.
. . . In this country written constitutions were deemed essential to protect the rights and liberties of the people against the encroachments of power delegated to their governments, and the provisions of Magna Charta were incorporated into bills of rights, They were limitations upon all the powers of government, legislative as well as executive and judicial. It necessarily happened, therefore, that as these broad and general maxims of liberty and justice hald in our system a different place and performed a different function from their position and office in English constitutional history and law, they would receive and justify a corresponding and more comprehensive interpretation. Applied in England only as guards against executive usurpation and tyranny, here they have become bulwarks also against arbitrary legislation; but in that application, as it would be incongruous to measure and restrict them by the ancient customary English law, they must be held to guaranty, not particular forms of procedure, but the very substance of individual rights to life, liberty, and property. . . .
The law of the land is not concerned merely with PROCEDURE. Our procedural forms can change over time. The law of the land--due process of law--guarantees the security of individual life, liberty, and property interests against unreasonable, arbitrary, oppressive government denials and deprivations. If you actually discussed this issue with our founders and suggested that the "original meaning" of the due process clause "means" that the government may deprive individuals of their life, liberty, or property interests so long as the government provides a fair PROCEDURE for doing so--they would scoff at you.
Debra_Law wrote:3. What the constitution forbids the government from accomplishing directly, it forbids the government from accomplishing indirectly.
Thomas wrote:In your jurisprudence, how does that apply to the Commerce Clause as an instrument of accomplishing all kinds of things indirectly that the federal government doesn't have a delegated power to do directly?
The Constitution delegates broad powers to the federal government to regulate commerce among the states. If you can give me an example how the federal government is indirectly accomplishing something it was directly forbidden to do via the Commerce Clause or another constitutional provision, I will try to address your question.